The nutshell kings: Why is human space settlement controversial in the first place?
Futures 143 (2022) 103023
Contents lists available at ScienceDirect
Futures
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/futures
The nutshell kings: Why is human space settlement controversial
in the first place?
Milan M. C´irkovi´c 1
Astronomical Observatory of Belgrade, Volgina 7, 11000 Belgrade, Serbia
ABSTRACT
Recent years have seen both a revival of space programs, mostly propelled by private industrys increasing interest, but also the emergence of strong
resistance to human space activities on several levels. This is partly a manifestation of a wider counter-Enlightenment Zeitgeist, as detectable in other
sectors of public life in the West, and partly a reaction against the widespread engagement of the private sector. While it still does not dominate the
discourse on space issues, space skepticism is surprisingly wide-ranging and decentralized phenomenon, gathering together heterogeneous strands
of thought from pro-Enlightenment liberals to rabid deep ecologyactivists to philosophical pessimists to antiglobalists of all colors. There has been
precious little in way of actively opposing this cultural trend so far, however. While space engineers and entrepreneurs conduct their business as
usual, there are plethora of risks hidden in this cultural climate, esp. if one adopts much repeated (and rarely adequately understood) maxim that
politics is downstream of culture. The present article will review major strands of thought within this big tentcultural movement, offer plausible
counter-arguments to space skeptics, and outline important cultural and public-outreach work which needs to be done to balance the scales.
I could be bounded in a nutshell and count myself a king of infinite space, were it not that I have bad dreams.
Hamlet, Act 2, Scene 2
1. Whos afraid of outer space?
Harvard psychologist Steven Pinker has recently successfully reimagined himself as the main defender of progress and the
Enlightenment values in todays largely cynical academia. Amidst fierce polemics with his opponents on both left and right, theres one
interesting aspect of (what any reasonable person would consider) progress where he is in complete accord with his opponents: he calls
space colonization a nonstarter, proposed by naifs.2 Nothing shouts the extent to which antispace sentiment has become
completely normative today louder than the fact that even a strong believer in science and progress like Pinker rejects what certainly
could be regarded as the grandest triumph of science and progressand not a single critic is taking him to task for it.
Imagine somebody coming up to the elders in ancient Greek city states to argue that the then fashionable program of setting up
colonies around the Mediterranean is an expression of their naivete. Imagine somebody approaching Prince Henry the Navigator to tell
him that all that business with caravels, compasses, cartography, sailing around Africa, etc. is a nonstarter. Imagineand this is by far
the most important analogysomebody preaching to our early ancestors in the Olduvai Gorge in northern Tanzania that they should
not under any circumstances leave their small, known, and cozy (in relative terms) environs and spread around. If we abstract away all
E-mail address: mcirkovic@aob.rs.
1 Also at Future of Humanity Institute, Faculty of Philosophy, University of Oxford, Suite 8, Littlegate House, 16/17 St Ebbes Street, Oxford, OX1
1PT, UK
2 Pinker (2018), p. 390.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.futures.2022.103023
Received 29 March 2022; Received in revised form 19 July 2022; Accepted 10 August 2022
Available online 19 August 2022
0016-3287/© 2022 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
M.M. C´irkovi´c
Futures 143 (2022) 103023
difficulties in communication, we can imagine this proto-Pinker to argue, with help of many data graphs and diagrams, that our
ancestors would be walking into a disaster if they tried to migrate around the globe, that mortality would be huge, that hardly anyone
would survive the migrations, that conditions at most places they would eventually inhabit would be worse than what they already had
at the Olduvai, that they will encounter new sicknesses and new predators. Who would have been willing to leave the lush East African
homeland to live in places such as Tibet, Alaska, Australian desert, Lapland, Amazonas, etc. Obviously, those very names would not
have existed if our ancestors had listened to such voices, Pinker-sophisticated or not. Whether the human species would have survived
in such a counterfactual history at the epoch corresponding to our year 2022 is very much open to debate; that its living conditions
would have been immensely worse than ours are is eminently not.
Thus, we are faced not by one, but by two cultural paradoxes. One is that while recent years have seen strong revival of space
programs in many quarters, we also perceive the emergence of strong resistance to human space activities along the corridors of
discourse. Ideological flagships of this negativity surge are the same old utopian visions of extremists on both right and left: sunny
future for the chosen nation, race, or class, for which sacrificing the present is justified. Both require a kind of local, parochial, closed
boxview of the world, incompatible with the cosmic future of humanity. During the space race of the 1950s and 60s, such tendencies
were present on the margins, but were kept in check by the very ideological polarization of the world. Leftist extremists, for instance,
could scoff at NASA, but could hardly afford not to applaud Sputnik, Gagarins flight, Soyuz, Tereshkova, and other achievements of the
Soviet space program.
Another paradox, however, is that even intellectuals who are manifestly pro-science and reason (who often self-identify as in­
heritors of the Enlightenment project) are still enslaved by manifestly narrow, parochial, and at least implicitly counter-Enlightenment
dogmas. Although there were some precursors, notably Hannah Arendts 1963 essay The Conquest of Space and the Stature of Man,
this is a phenomenon of newer vintage. Arguably, it was enabled by the ending of the Cold War and the rise of other concernswhich
decoupled the space issues from daily politics and relegated them to the lowest division of human projects.
This is partly a manifestation of a wider counter-Enlightenment Zeitgeist, as obvious in other sectors of culture and public life in the
West, and partly a reaction against the widespread engagement of the private sector in space. In sharp contrast to some of the previous
epochs in which important thinkers developed what could be called the cosmic vision of humanity (e.g., the era of H. G. Wells, Olaf
Stapledon, the Russian cosmists, J. B. S. Haldane, J. D. Bernal, etc.), the relevant ideas and memes are now transmitted at shockwave
velocity and impactor, as is here the case, confusemuch larger segments of the public opinion, electorate, and policy-makers.
Arguably, various brands of space skepticism have already reached a rather shrill and hysterical tone in many circles. In the media,
it is exemplified by two preposterous instances from The Atlantic (which had enthused about the Moon landings back then): one of them
being a pompous, ireful, and self-righteous attack targeting a poster and a joke (Kriss, 2017), the other exhibiting the level of geo­
centrism coupled with pettiness of concerns rarely seen since the trial of Galileo before the Roman Inquisition in 1633 (Stirone, 2021).
And the pitch of academia manifests itself on a spectrum from calls for excessive caution3 to fanciful scare-mongering about future Star
Wars, Dooms and Glooms which space settlement will allegedly entail4 to often hysterical political denunciations of space settlement as
an evil imperialist or racist or Big Pharma plot, depending on the favorite set of politically-incorrect scarecrows at any given moment.5
While space skepticism has not yet reached the level of prevalence some other cultural movements command, it is arguably
expanding its reach and even crosses-over with other major trends, notably climate anxieties, as testified for instance by a recent
blockbuster Dont Look Up (2021). Existing data on the lack of public support for space activities, sparse as such studies have been so
far, are rather solidly on the downside of the issue.6
In the rest of this article, I shall offer a plethora of plausible counter-arguments to space skeptics before outlining important cultural
and public-outreach work which needs to be done to balance the scales. Among topics which are impossible to cover in this format it is
important to mention two: the widely varying motivations of individual authors opposed to the human space settlement, which is a
topic for (at least) book-length treatment in and of itself, and the consequences of possible existence and properties of extraterrestrial
life on our envisioned space settlement prospects. Both are excessively complex topics which require a multidisciplinary analysis which
goes far beyond the scope of the present study.
2. Heavy on emotions, light on logic
Will space expansion really diminish the stature of Man [sic!]as Arendt would have us believe (Arendt, 2007)? Many modern
opponents of space exploration and settlement couldnt resist the temptation of latching onto Arendts deservedly huge prestige. It is of
foremost importance, however, to understand precisely what Arendt did and did not say. The single most important point of her essay,
originally published in 1963 and written somewhat earlier, is that the conquest of spacein the title is not to be taken literally; it
pertains less to specific space technology/astronautics (there is no indication that she was interested in the topic) than to the general
3 Weinberg (2013); Rees (2018); Szocik (2019). Even notable science-fiction (!) scholars and authors occasionally denounced space settlement in
this manner; cf. Westfahl (1997); Stross (2007).
4 Torres (2018); Kovic (2021).
5 Slobodian (2015); Vidaurri (2019); Gunderson, Stuart, and Petersen (2021).
6 Launius (2017). Note the gloomy conclusion of this ambitious study: A general public lack of support for expending many dollars on spaceflight
has been a fundamental reality of NASA since its beginning. It is not changing, and probably not changeable, in the predictive future. Accordingly,
NASAs quest for human spaceflights popular appeal remains an elusive goal.Apart from the emergence of New Space in recent years, there is no
clear data on any radical change in this respect since 2017.
2
M.M. C´irkovi´c
Futures 143 (2022) 103023
Enlightenment project of melioration through rational, scientific understanding and consequent reductive explanations. It could have
equally read the conquest of matter,” “the conquest of geography,or, perhaps most appropriately, the conquest of biology.
Without entering Arendts central concern that the effort to reduce all human accomplishment to mere biological processwill
cause our pride to disappear, and will ultimately threaten to lower/destroy the stature of (hu)man, we can see that the role of space is
indeed quite peripheral and immaterial here. One is tempted to ask in what sense does, for instance, deep-sea diving lower the stature
of (hu)man, since the conquest of the seasalso offers a technological fix for transcending our natural limitations. As members of
species which evolved in a very small part of East Africa, comprising about 6 millionths of Earths land real estate, with less than a
millionth of todays population at some point, to spread all over the globe (including many hostile locales) it is highly ironic to charge
the conquest of spacewith adverse consequences. Without the conquest of space, we would not have left the Olduvai Gorge and the
Great Rift Valley.
Clearly, both statureand dignityof humans are emotion-laden, fluid, and subjective terms in most of the construals used. One
notices that until very recently various authors argued that in-vitro fertilization or organ transplants violate human dignity; many
continue to hold similar views with respect to genetically modified foods, stem cell research, or even contraceptives. The Roman
Catholic church, for example in Poland, continues to hold IVF immoraland gruesome.7 While it was remote from Arendts ideas
and concerns, it is worrying to notice that in the course of the last half-century, the insistence on human dignity has become a province
of religious zealots and associated radical theologians.
Of course, one should notice that in the circles of bioethics and medical ethics, there is a growing tendency to downplay or avoid the
concept of dignity as vague or misleading, and to affirm the ethical positions not making use of it (undignified ethics8). A great deal
of progress, as history of science tells us in no uncertain terms, consists exactly in the rejection of vague and useless concepts in favor of
those which are more tangible, quantifiable, and informative.
On the Arendt bandwagon we find, strangely, both Leon Kass-like figures fighting to return religious thinking into mainstream
politics, culture, and strategic thinking, as well as those who hold the deep ecologyview that humankind is a scourge on Earth.
Bizarrely enough, these two seemingly antithetical strands of space skepticism humanist and antihumanist come together in these
confused times (similar to the well-known phenomenon that both left- and rightwing extremists now regularly join forces to protest
global capitalism, free markets, and other liberal cosmopolitan issues). Some examples will be given below.
The tracts of space skeptics abound with such an appeal to emotion. Thus the philosopher Phil Torres (2018): if such individuals
were to gain access to a ‘doomsday machineof some sort they would have sadistically, suicidally, and gleefully used it to annihilate
their conspecifics” – while the consequences are telling enough and suicidallyseems reasonable description, one wonders how would
the author know about sadisticallyand gleefully; if it is not the case, of course, that the emotionally loaded adverbs are used for
pure rhetorical effect. In the same category one may find Torress invoking of an obviously overblown and already proved to be
flawed at the time of writing scenario by Ray Kurzweil in which ecophages destroy the entire biosphere of Earth within ~90 min(p.
82). Fear-mongering reaches its unsurpassable apex with the following sentence: Consider the billions and billions and billions of
populations that could come to occupy the universe with 10 trillion galaxies and 1024 stars, each with its own traditions, boasting of
weapons that could destroy entire galaxies or even the entire universe(ibid., emphasis in the original). Indeed, once one reaches these
commanding heights of emotional demagoguery, where else to go? We need not be unduly alarmed by weapons that could destroy
entire galaxies or even the entire universe, which are bad science-fiction nonsense if ever there was one.9 Rather, one is impressed
how one Phil Torres in Philadelphia, PA, of 2018 perceives the problems facing inhabitants of 1024 stars in the AD 1 billion (or so)
better thanall those inhabitants themselves. Perhaps it is their own traditionswhich prevent them from seeing wisdom; if they
only were smart enough to accept Torress tradition, everything would have been just fine. I shall return to the underlying
Whiggish-like fallacy in the next section.
In contrast to Torress wide cosmological canvas, Lynda Williams engages in rather short-term fear-mongering when she asserts
without evidence that human missions to Mars do not guarantee the survival of the species, but rather, only the death of any member
who attempts the journey(Williams, 2010, p. 6). It is garnered by some quasi-religious appeal to emotion: If we accept the inevi­
tability of the destruction of Earth and its biosphere, then it is perhaps not too surprising that many people grasp at the last straw and
look toward the heavens for solutions and a possible resolution.(Ibid., p. 8) To cite another example in the same vein, the ethicist and
entrepreneur Marko Kovic in his comprehensive analysis of the risks of space settlement does not escape fear-mongering in the very
abstract of the paper claiming that it is uncertain whether meaningful space colonization governance can be established in the near
future, and before it is too late.Too late for what exactly? Abstract ends there and it is only vaguely sketched in the paper itself (one
7 Radkowska-Walkowicz (2018).
8 Cochrane (2010).
9 For elaboration of this embarrassingly trivial point, see C´irkovi´c (2019), Sections 3 and 4. See also Torress popular writings, e.g., https://nautil.
us/why-we-should-think-twice-about-colonizing-space-7525/ (last accessed July 3, 2022).
3
M.M. C´irkovi´c
Futures 143 (2022) 103023
option is establishment of reactionary colonieswhich is in itself a biased concept to which I shall return). The very phrase before it is
too lateis almost always a signpost of political demagoguery.10 The emotional state of false urgency is paradigmatic of the wider
concerns of the space skeptics.11
A rhetorical strategy similar to the appeal to emotion is assigning guilt by association. When the anthropologist John W. Traphagan
discusses the assumptions of a pro-space settlement author, he writes: A key component of the problem here is that assumptionsare
built from the perspectives of wealthy intellectual elites living in wealthy industrial societies and perhaps not coincidentally living in
Western societies that have been historical perpetrators of both colonialism and imperialism(Traphagan 2019, p. 48). Apart from the
usual blaming game, the not coincidentallyrhetorical device serves to underscore not only politically incorrect provenance, but also
to insinuate a causal link between pro-space arguments and the perceived sins of fathers. Which is additionally galling coming, as it
does, in a very brief paper affirming tribalism and ethnocentrism in the debates surrounding the human space settlement.
Philosophical pessimism as entailing space skepticism is exemplified by philosopher Robert Klee12: because we allegedly have no
cosmological future, we should not bother to become a cosmic civilization in the first place. Apart from being a self-fulfilling prophecy
peppered by rampant confirmation bias, this makes about as much sense as Woody Allens famous conclusion (in Annie Hall) that doing
homework has no point because cosmology tells us that the universe is expanding. And it is served with pretensions about being guided
by humanist philosophy at least Allens alter ego in the movie was 9 years old.
3. Playing fast and loose
While space skeptics are in general prone to label their opponents as adhering more to science-fiction than to science, their own
hypocritical use of SF ideas and themes passes mostly under the radar. Thus, when Torres assumes that (post)humans will one day
develop weapons that could destroy entire galaxies,13 he is engaging in rather unreasonable SF speculation. There are no indications
whatsoever that such superweapons are physically possible. And even if they are possible within some contrived philosophical sense of
the fullness of time, there is no need to worry about it, since there are literally thousands of more probable catastrophic scenarios
which could occur naturally and which bear no connection to the issue of space settlement.
While the notion of such superweapons seems in accordance with the laws of physics (barely), it is implausible that any actor could
really build one within the realistic constraint of space, time, and energy available in our real universe. In such cases of extreme
improbability, the better bet would perhaps be that our understanding of the laws of physics is actually incomplete and that such
astronomically improbable events are, in fact, prohibited. Of course, this does not mean that much smaller and realistic weapons could
not be deployed in an interplanetary or interstellar conflict. However, for anyone except a committed nihilist, worrying about such
wars and weapons of the distant future would be quite hypocritical, taking into account the plain fact that present-day humans already
possess weaponry capable of destroying our planetary habitat. This straightforward threat will certainly remain, to our detriment, as
long as humanity is limited to one planetary habitat.
A barely coherent panicking such as Torress over galaxy-destroying superweaponsis hardly alone in this respect. A similar case
is made by Kovic, who decries potential reactionary colonieshumans could possibly establish in space14 as if lecturing our de­
scendants centuries or millennia in the future on a present-day ideological basis is anything but unbelievably arrogant presumption.
This is a kind of inverted Whiggish fallacy in historiography: while Whig historians castigated people of past epochs for their alleged
sins against the present-day political and moral standards, the space skeptics choose to castigate future people for their alleged sins
against the present-day political and moral standards. If the original Whiggish fallacy is a blind alley of hubris and myopia, the inverted
version is doubly ludicrous.
The entire cottage industry of Hobbesian virtue signalling as applied to the distant and likely postbiological future is devoid of sense
and rationality. (Note in passing that the entire set of Hobbesian arguments has historically been antithetical to the human dignity
arguments, Hobbesian materialism being dismissive of the very notion of special dignityaccorded to human biological machines.
This is just another example of internal conflict or incoherency inherent to the patchwork quilt of space skepticism.).
The insistence of Tomasik (2011), Torres, Kovic and some other authors on suffering risks to be allegedly caused by space set­
tlement sounds wise and noble at a glance until one realizes that it is grounded in a very narrow ethical framework (negative
utilitarianism). Since very many other positions are possible and legitimate in moral philosophy, it is clearly dishonest to downplay the
fact that adherents of deontology, virtue ethics, contractualism, positive utilitarianism or pragmatic ethics, among others, are not
obliged to follow skeptical arguments based on the suffering risks. Especially when the arguments are inherently speculative. Negative
utilitarianism is very much a minority view and to insist that it sets the ethical standards for the grandest human endeavors is similar to
10 E.g., when used by Donald Trump in a tweet of September 17, 2020, 11:56:59 (https://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/documents/tweets-
september-172020, last accessed July 3, 2022) or equally repulsive by Bernie Sanders in the foreword and blurb to Teachout (2020).
11 Note that there is no necessary symmetry in this respect between proponents and opponents of space settlement. If space settlement is regarded
as a natural and reasonable evolutionary extension of humanitys ecological niche and the best chance or even precondition for human survival and
flourishingas it is assumed in the present manuscript (and as it is argued by most space settlement advocates)there is asymmetry in treating
emotional appeal to the issue. To receive appeals to emotion equivocally on both sides would be similar to equivocating between appeals to emotion
in, say, the debates about slavery, women voting rights, or climate change.
12 Klee (2017).
13 Torres (2019), p. 82.
14 Kovic (2021), p. 9.
4
M.M. C´irkovi´c
Futures 143 (2022) 103023
insistence that, e.g., Mormons or Sikhs set standards of religious observance for all humankind.
Another popular anti-space canard is that we do need space research, but robots are betterat it. Proponents fail to address
questions such as: How could robots be better on Moon, Mars or Titan and not on Earth? If they are fully capable of such sophisticated
activity as space research, how pray tell comes about they are not fully capable of rearing children, composing operas or making
political decisions? Or, perhaps, how could not robots be better than humans in writing anti-space tracts? There is no obvious metric on
which space research is easier or less complex than those tasks (or myriad others). Note that the effectiveness of this argument is
completely orthogonal to the motivation in presenting it: while it is clear that many authors (e.g., Weinberg, Schwartz) are motivated
by sincere humanist desire to prevent human deaths in space which are perhaps as unavoidable as human deaths on high seas ever
were it is easy to argue that many alternative motivations are in play within the wide spectrum of anti-space activism: from
speciesism to simple laziness and extreme risk-aversion. As emphasized in the introductory section, the detailed motivational analysis
of the anti-space arguments would require a book-length treatment and is beyond the scope of the present manuscript.
In a sense, the robot argument is a reductio ad absurdum of space skepticism. Starting from allegedly humanist premises, space
skeptics end up affirming the obsolescence of humanity. While there can be no doubt that some particular aspects of space research are
optimal for robotization, to argue that this applies to the entire spectrum of space research activities is a dangerous antihuman
nonsense. At best, it invokes a Blade Runner-like future of specieist discrimination and police authoritarianism necessary to keep robots
Off World. At worst, it is a prelude to Cˇapeks R.U.R., where the superior robot-based economy leads to unavoidable extinction of
humanity on Earth (and, since they failed to settle other worlds, everywhere).
4. Pars pro toto
Most space skeptics argue onlyfor delaying human space exploration/colonization, as an allegedly realistmiddle ground be­
tween proponents of the cosmic future of humanity and those who would burn them at stake as heretics. The argument suggests that
right now it is not a good time for space settlement, but at some point in the future the time will be just right.15
When exactly, though? Since there is no known natural timescalefor any particular occurrence in cultural evolution, it is hard to
assess this argument. How big delay is sufficient? Or optimal? Or desirable? The answer until we solve all problems on Earthis
nonsense there will always be some problems on Earth. The fact that I am writing and you are reading this now (instead of working
directly on space science/technology), could be construed as supportive of some degree of delay. At the other extreme, someone who
would claim that human space activities should be postponed until the Sun enters the red giant phase, should not be taken seriously in
the first place.16 Usually, we are seeing vague construals such as it is a task for the distant futureor empty platitudes such as once we
have figured out how to make life on Earth work insustainable way.17
There is no structural difference between the argument for delaying space colonization and the infamous argument for delaying
climate action. In both cases there is a gasping presumption that we shall inevitably be better off in the future than we are now; specific
climate change mitigation measures which are expensive today will, allegedly, become much cheaper in the future, so we should
undertake them 20 or 200 or 2000 years from now, say. Doing otherwise would be tantamount to taking from the poor (present) to give
to the rich (future). Irresponsibility and naïvet´e of such a view defy belief. Adverse consequences of climate change are what already
threatens to a significant degree global economic prosperity today, which is a precondition for the decrease in price tomorrow.
While the question which model of temporal discounting best represents reality still lacks a clear answer, nobody seriously doubts the
necessity of such discounting in the futures studies (e.g., Tonn & Stiefel, 2014).
Why should it differ for human space settlement? Insofar as the latter is regarded as decreasing the risk of human extinction and
increasing the robustness of human civilization, the parallel holds. While it is reasonable to expect that barring crises and catastrophes!
the direct cost of human space settlements will decrease in the future, one is still entitled to the same skepticism toward it as in the
case of climate change: leaving the brunt of work to ones descendants betrays cowardice in face of responsibility. Coupled with
corrosive influence of social constructivism on the public perception of relevant science (Hansson, 2020), such attitude abounds in
global dangers and threats.
The delay argument is usually bolstered by a pars pro toto fallacy: skeptical discourses which are focused on a single small facet of
the entire vast front of space expansion. In cartoonish terms this reasoning can be represented as follows:
(A) Proponents of space settlement often express their desire/goal/intention to settle Mars.
(B) Long-term habitation of Mars is impossible/unfeasible/undesirable.
Hence,
(C) Proponents of space settlement have no case.
This is not only formally wrong in the sense that the premises do not entail the conclusion, but willfully misleading on several
15 Weinberg (2013), Schwartz (2019), or Szocik (2019).
16 Thus Williams (2010): So yes, we are doomed, but we have five billion years, plus or minus a few hundred million, to plan our extraterrestrial
escape.Nice to note that there are central-planners who openly entertain the Five Billion Year Plan.
17 Weinberg (2013); Williams (2010).
5
M.M. C´irkovi´c
Futures 143 (2022) 103023
counts. Obviously, Mars is a very, very, very small part of the surrounding universe. For all worthiness of the pursuit of settling Mars,
even if the premise (B) is granted, this certainly does not exhaust the list of possible targets for space settlement, especially so many
decades after the epochal work of Gerard ONeill, who persuasively argued for entirely artificial habitats, or those constructed by
adapting small bodies (asteroids/cometary nuclei) for human habitation. Therefore, even if Mars or the Moon or Ganymede turn out to
be impractical for settlement, many options remain, in the main Asteroid Belt, in the Kuiper belt, among NEOs, and in convenient
orbits around Earth or other bodies. Often shrill criticism of terraforming belongs here as well: whatever intrinsic merits or demerits of
terraforming there are, its practice is and will likely forever be a very, very small part of the space settlement advocacy.
This side of the story has nothing to do with the intrinsic likelihood of the premise (B). I find that likelihood low, and we may have
various opinions on that, but the onus of proof is on skeptics. Again, imagine a prophetic voice telling one of our ancestors, fresh out of
the Olduvai Gorge, that they should not migrate, since it is so cold in (what will become) Scandinavia or Alaska, so wet in Japan or
Brazil, so dry in Sahara or the Australian interior, etc.
5. Conclusions: the poverty of skepticism
In the course of this paper, I have surveyed a wide and often wild array of arguments of space skeptics; as far as possible I have
refrained from presenting the positive case for space, since many authors have done that in more masterly and comprehensive manner
(e.g., ONeill, 1977; Tsiolkovsky, 2004; Beech, 2007; Musk, 2017, 2018; Green, 2019; Sivolella, 2019; Zubrin, 1999, 2019). At the
present level of knowledge and understanding, almost all skeptical arguments are either too vague/emotional to be properly engaged,
or fail to meet serious critical scrutiny, or are not, in fact, opposed to the space expansion generally, criticizing only a particular
objectionable segment of it. In addition, space skepticism lacks internal coherency; we are dealing with a hodge-podge of various
complaints and peeves instead, often grounded in totally opposed and incompatible ideologies (humans are planetary cancer which
should not be allowed to spreadvs. humans are too precious to be risked or exploited in space settlements). There are, however, still
two key questions to address.
5.1. Do we need to worry?
One may think that all the media/academic hot air does not really impact the progress of space technology and development. While
NASA and the small bunch of its analogs may hire marketing teams to counter the skeptic worries (often in a rather hypocritical
manner, hence confirminginstead of dispellingparanoiac and conspiratorial assertions of the critics), their piece of the cosmic cake
is getting smaller. Most engineers and mission personnel may endorse the business as usualattitude. This would be a serious mistake,
similar to the one committed by most in the natural sciences when faced with the onslaught of postmodernism, identity politics and
critical theory nonsense in academia: it took only two decades from the Sokal Hoax to reach the stage in which NASA organizes Mission:
Equity and gets involved in re-christening transneptunian objects in agreement with the newest pol-correct fads (meanwhile debating
merits of the scandalous $4.1 bn price tag for a single Artemis launch18), while Cornell University offers shockingly foolish nonsense in
racial cosmologyas a course.19 So, recent experience demonstrates that stupid is contagiousand is moving in the direction of
science and engineering. The fact that space skepticism is not sufficiently dominant in the public and cultural sphere to directly
obstruct specific programs and activities should not lull us into complacency about its destructive and confusing potential.
One may ask a pertinent question about the relevance of the public sphere and cultural climate in the epoch in which most space
industry passed from the government to private actors. Clearly, it is unrealistic to assume that governments will relinquish their role in
directing and regulating our space efforts any time soon. Governments are and are likely to remain for quite some time significant
developers of technologies that form the foundation of new space industry segments and industries. In such situation the main issue is
what regulatory pressures and other statist issues are optimal from the point of view of efficient space exploration and settlement.
While the space skepticism could arguably be less impactful in the mostly privatized New Space context, it can still poison the public
discourse and lead to completely unnecessary and irrational tensions in culture and society. So, yes, we need to worry.
5.2. What is to be done?
This is the real crux of the issue. There has been precious little in way of activelly opposing the cultural trend so far. While space
engineers and enterpreneurs conduct their business as usual, there are a plethora of risks hidden in this cultural climate, esp. if one
adopts the much repeated (and rarely adequately understood) maxim that politics is downstream of culture. We need more free
debate on these issues which is becoming more and more difficult in the current authoritarian atmosphere. On the tactical level, there
are things space advocates should learn from the skeptics: appeals to emotions, social slant, humanist rhetoric with the advantage that
space advocacy is, for a change, a truly humanist program. Education in STEM is of paramount importance and there is simply no
excuse for policy discussions on any level by societal actors often without any exposure to STEM fields. More clear critical thinking will
contribute to suppression of the fashionable cosmic pessimism” – often feeding on the ignorance which is at best confusing and at
worst extremely dangerous as far as the future of humanity is concerned.
Finally, a change in the overall mindset is highly desirable. It is only our own intellectual inertia and laziness which makes us short-
18 https://oig.nasa.gov/docs/IG-22003.pdf, last accessed July 3, 2022.
19 https://complit.cornell.edu/news/featured-course-black-holes-race-and-cosmos, last accessed July 6, 2022.
6
M.M. C´irkovi´c
Futures 143 (2022) 103023
sighted and devoid of true vision. In a parable due to Kierkegaard and retold by Borges, Danish priests initially offered indulgences for
undertaking North Pole expeditions. Since such expeditions are difficult and require considerable courage and effort, priests gradually
relaxed the conditions under which they defined participation in such an expedition. At the end, they concluded that any travel
whatsoever, like sailing from Copenhagen to London, or traveling to a Sunday picnic, qualifies as a true North Pole expedition. This is a
perfect metaphor for the global state of self-indulgence, complacency, and cowardice (with honorable exceptions) about the cosmic
future of humanity. While a Tsiolkovsky, a Stapledon, or an ONeill boldly proclaimed our cosmic destiny a century or half a century
ago, while the geniuses of Clarke and Kubrick produced a magnificent space vision in 1960s, todays NASA and related organizations
engage in postmodern virtual nonsense. The ongoing pandemic of SARS-CoV-2 should, if anything, teach us about fragility of the
terrestrial civilization under even mild threats of either natural or anthropogenic origin.
As Shakespeare understood, our nutshell kings would be perfectly fine except for the bad dreams theyre having. Their bad
dreams, full of jealousy (and pathological politics of jealousy), geocentrism, anthropocentrism, parochialism both cosmic and
terrestrial, short-termism morphing into reckless short-sightedness, politically correct virtue signaling, fake pragmatism and false
precaution, as well as myriad other tools of concern trolling, are certainly a thing in todays world. Freud (and Otto Rank and many
subsequent psychoanalysts/existentialists) would certainly connect such bad dreams with the trauma of birth; going a single step
further than Tsiolkovsky, one may evoke Earth not as the cradle, but as the womb of an emerging cosmic civilization. Leaving it is
traumatic and violent. No wonder the nutshell kings are horrified by the prospect. They would prefer not to be born.
Those nightmares should be contrasted with noble dreams of the great visionaries of the world, of Fedorovs and Stapledons, of
Tsiolkovskys and Buckminster Fullers, of Teslas and Dysons, of Clarkes and Kubricks, of Lems and ONeills, of Sagans and Kurzweils
and Sandbergs and Musks and the unknown leaders of migrations from Olduvai. Great minds not just of Earth, but of the universe
itself, the true cosmopolitans (= citizens of the cosmos), inheritors of truly inspiring evolutionary traditions of expanding into available
ecological and creative niches. This wonderful planet is indeed too minuscule to confine those noble dreams which indeed belong to
the entire universe.
Every one of us is free to choose the kind of dreams to adhere to.
The nutshell will be cracked.
Acknowledgements
Three anonymous referees have kindly supplied useful comments resulting in significant improvement upon an early version of this
manuscript. Pleasant discussions with Milica Banovi´c, Keith Mansfield, Slobodan Popovi´c, Srdja Jankovi´c, Mark Walker, Paul Gilster,
Bojan Stojanovi´c, Slobodan Perovi´c, and Claire Berlinski are also hereby acknowledged.
References
Arendt, H. [1963] 2007, The Conquest of Space and the Stature of Man,New Atlantis Fall issue, 4355 (http://www.thenewatlantis.com/publications/the-
conquest-of-space-and-the-stature-of-man, last accessed August 15, 2020).
Beech, M. (2007). Rejuvenating the sun and avoiding other global catastrophes. New York: Springer.
C´irkovi´c, M. M. (2019). Space colonization remains the only long-term option for humanity: a reply to Torres. Futures, 105, 166173.
Dont Look Up. (2021). DVD, dir. A. McKay. Los Gatos, California: Netflix.
Cochrane, A. (2010). Undignified bioethics. Bioethics, 24, 234241.
Green, B. P. (2019). Self-preservation should be humankinds first ethical priority and therefore rapid space settlement is necessary. Futures, 110, 3537.
Gunderson, R., Stuart, D., & Petersen, B. (2021). In Search of Plan (et) B: Irrational Rationality, Capitalist Realism, and Space Colonization. Futures, 134, Article
102857.
Hansson, S. O. (2020). Social constructionism and climate science denial. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 10(37).
Klee, R. (2017). Human expunction. International Journal of Astrobiology, 16, 379388.
Kovic, M. (2021). Risks of space colonization. Futures, 126, Article 102638.
Kriss, S. (2017), Think Twice About Escaping Earth to an Exoplanet,The Atlantic March 2017, https://www.theatlantic.com/science/archive/2017/03/space-
travel-wont-save-you-from-capitalism/518853/(last accessed September 27, 2021).
Launius, R. D. (2017). NASAs quest for human spaceflight popular appeal. Social Science Quarterly,, 98, 12161232.
Musk, E. (2017). Making humans a multi-planetary species. New Space, 5, 4661.
Musk, E. (2018). Making life multi-planetary. New Space, 6, 211.
ONeill, G. K. (1977). The high frontier: human colonies in space. New York: William Morrow & Company.
Pinker, S. (2018). Enlightenment now: The case for reason, science, humanism, and progress. New York: Penguin Books.
Radkowska-Walkowicz, M. (2018). How the political becomes private: In vitro fertilization and the Catholic Church in Poland. Journal of Religion and Health, 57,
979993.
Rees, M. (2018). On the future. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Schwartz, J. S. (2019). Space settlement: whats the rush? Futures, 110, 5659.
Sivolella, D. (2019). Space mining and manufacturing: off-world resources and revolutionary engineering techniques. Cham: Springer Nature.
Slobodian, R. E. (2015). Selling space colonization and immortality: a psychosocial, anthropological critique of the rush to colonize Mars. Acta Astronautica, 113,
89104.
Stirone, S. (2021). Mars Is a Hellhole. https://www.theatlantic.com/ideas/archive/2021/02/mars-is-no-earth/618133/(last accessed September 27, 2021).
Stross, C. (2007). The High Frontier, Redux. https://www.antipope.org/charlie/blog-static/2007/06/the_high_frontier_redux.html(last accessed June 27, 2022).
Szocik, K. (2019). Should and could humans go to Mars? Yes, but not now and not in the near future. Futures, 105, 5466.
Teachout, Z. (2020). Break em up: recovering our freedom from big ag, big tech, and big money. New York: All Points Book/St. Martins Publishing Group.
Tonn, B., & Stiefel, D. (2014). Human extinction risk and uncertainty: assessing conditions for action. Futures, 63, 134144.
7
M.M. C´irkovi´c
Futures 143 (2022) 103023
Tomasik, B. (2011). Risks of Astronomical Future Suffering. Foundational ResearchInstitute report (https://longtermrisk.org/files/risks-of-astronomical-future-
suffering.pdf) (last accessed July 20, 2022).
Torres, P. (2018). Space colonization and suffering risks: reassessing the ‘Maxipok Rule. Futures, 100, 7485.
Tsiolkovsky, K. E. (2004). Selected works. Miami: University Press of the Pacific.
Vidaurri, M. (2019). What happens when you leave empty seats at the table? The Space Review, 21, 2019.
Weinberg, S. (2013). Response: against manned space flight programs. Space Policy, 29, 229230.
Westfahl, G. (1997). The case against space. Science Fiction Studies, 24, 193206.
Williams, L. (2010). Irrational dreams of space colonization. Peace Review, 22, 48.
Zubrin, R. (1999). Entering space: creating a spacefaring civilization. New York: Jeremy P. Tarcher/Putnam.
Zubrin, R. (2019). The Case for space: how the revolution in spaceflight opens up a future of limitless possibility. Amherst: Prometheus Books.
8