Organising in the Anthropocene: an ontological outline for ecocentric theorising
Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
Contents lists available at ScienceDirect
Journal of Cleaner Production
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/jclepro
Organising in the Anthropocene: an ontological outline for ecocentric
theorising
Pasi Heikkurinen a, *, Jenny Rinkinen b, Timo Jarvensivu c, Kristoffer Wilen d, Toni Ruuska e
a University of Leeds, Sustainability Research Institute, Leeds, LS2 9JT, United Kingdom
b Lancaster University, DEMAND Centre, Department of Sociology, Lancaster, LA1 4YD, United Kingdom
c Aalto University School of Business, Department of Marketing, Helsinki, 00100, Finland
d Hanken School of Economics, Department of Marketing, Helsinki, 00100, Finland
e Aalto University School of Business, Department of Management Studies, Helsinki, 00100, Finland
article info
Article history:
Received 27 August 2015
Received in revised form
3 December 2015
Accepted 9 December 2015
Available online 23 December 2015
Keywords:
Anthropocene
Ecocentric
Ecocentrism
Ecosophy
Ontology
Organisation
abstract
As a response to anthropogenic ecological problems, a group of organisation scholars have acknowledged
the importance of ecocentric theorising that takes materiality and non-human objects seriously. The
purpose of this article is to examine the philosophical basis of ecocentric organisation studies and
develop an ontological outline for ecocentric theorising in the Anthropocene. The paper identies the
central premises of ecocentric organisations from the previous literature, and complements the theory
with a set of ontological qualities common to all objects. The study draws on recent advances in object-
oriented and ecological philosophies to present three essential qualities of objects, namely autonomy,
uniqueness, and intrinsicality. The paper discusses how these qualities are critical in reclaiming the lost
credibility and practical relevance of ecocentrism in both organisational theory and the sustainability
sciences in general. To organise human activities in a sustainable manner in the new geological era, a
new ontology is needed that not only includes materiality and non-humans in the analysis, but also leads
to an ecologically and ethically broader understanding of ecospheric beings and their relationships.
© 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
1. Introduction
In the era of the Anthropocene (Crutzen and Stoermer, 2000;
Crutzen, 2002), it is increasingly acknowledged that the way hu-
man life is organised is ecologically damaging and jeopardises the
existence of most beings (MA, 2005; Barnosky et al., 2011; IPCC,
2014). Especially since the Industrial Revolution, or more pre-
cisely the invention of the steam engine, the biosphere and its local
ecosystems have undergone radical changes in terms of rising
temperatures and a reduction in biodiversity (Zalasiewicz et al.,
2008; Barnosky et al., 2012). Climate scientists have recorded a
worrying global temperature rise of 1 C since the early twentieth
century (NASA/GISS, 2014), while biologists and palaeontologists
have suggested that the sixth mass extinction might be on the
horizon if the current rate of species loss continues (Barnosky et al.,
* Corresponding author. Tel.: þ44 (0)113 343 9631.
E-mail addresses: p.heikkurinen@leeds.ac.uk (P. Heikkurinen), jenny.rinkinen@
lancaster.ac.uk (J. Rinkinen), timo.jarvensivu@aalto.(T. Jarvensivu), kristoffer.
wilen@hanken.(K. Wilen), toni.ruuska@aalto.(T. Ruuska).
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jclepro.2015.12.016
0959-6526/© 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
2011, 2012; Ceballos et al., 2015). These two changes in the envi-
ronment are assumed to be causally related, so that global warming
is leading to biodiversity loss, as ecosystems and their organisms
are unable to adapt to the rapid climatic changes in their habitat
(MA, 2005). To avert further damage, continued population growth,
excessive resource use and environmental deterioration are chal-
lenges that humanity must deal with within the next few decades
(Steffen et al., 2007), and arguably, the sooner the better (see e.g.,
Ceballos et al., 2015).
Despite the severity of the ecological challenge, and particularly
the signicant role that the organisation of production has in the
climate crisis (Barnosky et al., 2012; IPCC, 2014), ecological ques-
tions have remained at the periphery of contemporary organisation
theory, as reviewed by Cunha et al. (2008). Rather than focussing on
the non-human and material aspects of the world, organisational
enquiries have tended to emphasise the role of humans and non-
material aspects of the organisation (Fleetwood, 2005;
Orlikowski, 2010). It follows that organisational studies are in-
clined to reproduce the anthropocentric and antirealist philo-
sophical tradition of science, as the human experience is favoured
at the expense of the non-human world. The absence of an
706
P. Heikkurinen et al. / Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
ecological perspective on organising human activity seems likely to
lead the way deeper into the Anthropocene with unpleasant con-
sequences not only for the human species but also for the
ecosystem as a whole.
The lack of organisational theorising from an ecological
perspective was rst noticed in the mid-1990s, when the rela-
tionship between organisations and the natural environment
attracted scholarly attention (Shrivastava, 1994; Gladwin et al.,
1995; Clair et al., 1996). Some of the early scholars discussed, for
instance, the relevance of organisational activities to developments
such as overpopulation and overconsumption (Starik and Rands,
1995), as well as the limitations of an anthropocentric worldview
in dealing with ecological problems (Purser et al., 1995). Thus,
instead of continuing to position human actors above other beings
and interpreting the world in terms of human values, these scholars
developed and called for ecocentric approaches in the ontological,
epistemological, and axiological domains of organisation studies
(Shrivastava, 1994, 1995; Purser et al., 1995; Starik and Rands, 1995;
Starik, 1995).
While the call was not immediately taken up, a few organisa-
tional scholars have recently expressed signs of ecocentric theo-
rising by embedding social actors in the ecosystem (Whiteman and
Cooper, 2000), recognising the interconnectedness of all actors in
the ecosystem (Valente, 2012; Newton, 2002), and advancing
ethical considerations for the non-human world (Gosling and Case,
2013; Ezzamel and Willmott, 2014). Critics of ecocentrism, how-
ever, have continued to question the necessity and practicality of
ecocentric thought, as well as the underpinnings of its worldview
(Hanna, 1996). An intellectually well-founded critique on ecocen-
trism has been presented on the feasibility of reordering the human
relationship with the natural environment, and on the dualistic
representations of nature and humans (Newton, 2002). These
fundamental, yet constructive strictures on ecocentrism, coming
from both the managerial and sociological sides of organisation
studies, invite environmental scientists to revisit the philosophical
foundations of ecocentric theory.
Against this background, the purpose of this paper is to examine
the philosophical basis of ecocentric organisation studies, and
develop an ontological outline for ecocentric theorising in the
Anthropocene. The study is guided by the following research
questions: (a) what are the central premises of ecocentric organi-
sations in the previous literature, and (b) how might these premises
be complemented in order to respond to the criticism of ecocentric
thought and advance ontology for an ecological organisation?
Without a thorough discussion on the basic categories of being
and how they relate to each other (particularly those between
human and non-human objects), the task of advancing ecocentric
theory becomes not only extremely demanding, but can also
threaten the credibility of the approach and attract criticism of a
failure to deliver practical value. The importance of focussing on
ontological questions is reinforced by the premise that the way
humans perceive objectseand their relationsewill inuence the
way things are (and will be) organised. Hence, the nature of objects
is crucial in the search for ecological organisations, including sus-
tainable modes of production.1
The paper begins with a brief introduction to the questions of
ontology in organisation studies and provides an overview of the
1 A sustainable mode of production as imagined in this study is not limited to the
early German concept on sustainability (Nachhaltigkeit), which appeared in 1712 in
the writings of von Carlowitz to indicate how monetary prots could be made
from nature by obtaining optimum sustainable yields(Martinez-Alier, 2014, p. 38)
but is instead in line with the idea of strong sustainability (e.g., Pearce and
Atkinson, 1993; Beckerman, 1995; Ayres et al., 2001).
challenges related to the Anthropocene: the current geological era.2
The study proceeds to review the ways previous studies in the eld
of the organisation and the natural environment have con-
ceptualised humanenature relationships, and also to identify the
central premises of ecocentric organisations. To advance ecocentric
theorising, the paper draws on object-oriented and ecological
philosophies to arrive at a set of essential qualities of objects. Lastly,
it proposes an ontological outline for further studies and concludes
by discussing the implications of the outline for ecological practice
and theory.
2. Ontological questions in the age of humans
The eld of organisation studies has undergone several intel-
lectual redirections or turns within its relatively short history
(Reed, 2005). Some of these turns have dealt with the means of
acquiring and analysing data, while others have focused more on
the assumptions related to the nature of knowledge and reality, or
ontology. The ontological position of a person, community, or turn,
could be described as a way of understanding the nature of reality.
An ontology can also more directly, and quite literally, be thought of
as how the world is: what exists, and so what are the primary
entities of concern in any given field, and what are their most
general features and relationships(Spash, 2012, p. 37). Moreover,
as ontologies deal with the question of existence and being, they
are often considered the most profound concerns in scientic
enquiries.
Fleetwood (2005, p. 197) describes the ontological discussion in
organisation studies as ambiguous, which makes it difcult to get
to the bottom of ontological claims and, of course, to locate the
source of any ontological errors. Ontological discussions often also
mix with epistemological questions (that relate to knowledge) and
axiological questions (that relate to value), which make them even
more complex and challenging to grasp. Owing to its often-
assumed lack of practical implications for managers and its weak
relevance to what might be called the publication rat race, ontology
(as a study of being and existence) might also have a forbidding
echo for some organisation theorists. However, if scholars seek
ecologically advanced understandings of organisations, the exam-
ination of ontologies may offer not only prolic grounds and
stimulating avenues in the quest for considering different objects
and their relations, such as man-made organisations and the nat-
ural environment, but may also be unavoidable in the current times
of ecological, and sociocultural, turmoil. The climatic and geological
changes are arguably pressing humans to rethink their relationship
with other humans and the non-human world through recent
phenomena like climate refugees and mass extinctions.
The ontologies in organisation studies have recently been
heavily inuenced by the cultural, linguistic, post-structural or
postmodern approaches that build on an idea of socially con-
structed realities (Fleetwood, 2005). For an ecocentric inquiry, this
development can be considered problematic because, in the anti-
realist ontology, a world does not exist independent of human
perception, and because the proponents of antirealism do not
subscribe to any causal scientic independence of matters of fact in
the world (Maki, 2008). To put it bluntly, if the causality of human
action and ecological harm cannot be propounded with any degree
of certainty, then protective measures (e.g., conservation efforts)
are difcult to justify and legitimise.
2 A team of scientists led by Jan Zalasiewicz announced that in 2017 a decision
will be made on whether the current geological epoch will be ofcially re-named
(Schwagerl, 2013).
P. Heikkurinen et al. / Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
707
According to a recent report by the Intergovernmental Panel on
Climate Change, the main causes of global warming are anthro-
pogenic greenhouse gas emissions, which are in turn undesired
consequences of economic and population growth (IPCC, 2014), and
particularly the former (UNEP, 2011; Lorek and Spangenberg, 2014).
The growth of economies (measured in gross national product) and
in the number of human inhabitants on the planet, have meant a
rising demand for food, mobility, housing and other goods and
services (Latouche, 2009; Jackson, 2011). The production of these
goods and services has led not only to growing pressure on the
atmosphere through emissions, but also to growing pressure on
land and water occasioned by their utilisation for production pur-
poses: During the course of the 20th century, average resource use
per capita merely doubled,while the global annual material
extraction increased [] by a factor of eight(UNEP, 2011, p. 17e18).
The use of the term Anthropocene e the Age of Humans e is apt to
describe this current era of global climate change and negative
human inuences on ecological processes (Crutzen and Stoermer,
2000; Crutzen, 2002; Zalasiewicz et al., 2008).3 In ontological
terms, this signies that humans are not only observers of the
Anthropocene but a central causal factor in the unfolding of reality:
a dominant ingredient of the planetary ecosystem.
For a large part of the scientic community, it is apparent that
ecosystems are now setting limits to the expansion of organised
human activity (Rockstrom et al., 2009; Steffen et al., 2015). Un-
sustainable development has been enabled by medical and other
technical advances, by an unequal global exchange of energy and
other natural resources (Hornborg, 2014), particularly fossil fuels
(Wrigley, 2010), as well as a major growth in agriculture and animal
husbandry (Crutzen and Steffen, 2003). In terms of material limits,
non-renewable natural resources are running out and renewable
resources are being consumed at a faster rate than they can renew
(e.g., Lorek and Spangenberg, 2014). Concerning less tangible limits,
again, the atmospheric carbon dioxide concentration has been
found to be too great and the global nitrogen cycle to be too dis-
rupted to ensure a safe operating space for humanity and other
species (Rockstrom et al., 2009; Steffen et al., 2015). These esti-
mates concerning the state of the planet are certainly surrounded
by uncertainties, but the important point here is that if humans are
to steer away from the worst-case scenarios of collapsing ecosys-
tems and civilisations, human activities should be reorganised in
ecologically sustainable ways (Goodland and Daly, 1996).
In ontological terms, an ecologically substantive understanding
of beingin the Anthropocene epoch thus calls for a more realist
approach in organisation studies. Considering an organisation
merely as a socially constructed phenomenon might lead to over-
looking the material basis of all human activity in the ecosystem.
Any such exclusion of materiality and non-human objects from the
analysis is not only scientically limited, but also highly dangerous
if it propounds a worldview where ecological destruction is not
considered problematic beyond human interests. Thus, without
doubt, in certain instances it might be appropriate, justiable
and eminently sensible to look for something other than human
language in order to appreciate the force of phenomena like human
3 It is important to note what Graham Harman (in Koot and Grootveld, 2015, p. 1)
expressed in a recent interview: [the] Anthropocene Epoch is not an Anthropo-
centric Epoch, because it highlights the fragility of the human species rather than
human supremacy. This split between the Anthropocene and the Anthropocentric
compels us to recognise an important philosophical distinction that is seldom
acknowledged. Namely, the fact that humans are involved as ingredients in the
creation of some entity does not entail that the entity has no autonomous reality
apart from humans. The Anthropocene climate is generated by humans and inde-
pendently mysterious to us, and the same holds for other elds that have been
anthropocenefrom the start: human society, art, economics.
responsibility and harm; simply recurring to discourse may often be
unsatisfactory(Holt and Mueller, 2011, p. 82). Moreover, denying
reality independent of the human subject is disturbingly anthro-
pocentric, which again is shown to be limited in its usefulness in
solving the complex ecological problems that organisations now
face (Purser et al., 1995).
Against this call for a new ontological frame, the next section
reviews and discusses the main premises of, and advances in,
ecological organisation literature. In the current study an ecological
organisation refers to those organisational orderings that take place
within the bioregional and global, and material boundaries of
ecosystems, and hence embrace the existence and prosperity of
humans, as well as other beings.
3. Organisations and the natural environment
In the Western tradition, the origins of ecological thought on
organising human action can be traced to inuential North-
American texts such as Nature (Emerson, 1836), Walden (Thoreau,
1854), and Silent Spring (Carson, 1962). In Europe, important early
contributions to ecological thinking were Capital: Critique of Polit-
ical Economy (Marx, [1867] 1992) and The Technological Society
(Ellul, [1954] 1964). The authors of these far-sighted texts identied
and reported on a development whereby humans are becoming
increasingly distanced from the natural environment (i.e. non-
man-made objects), but are becoming a greater force in shaping
it (i.e. turning non-man-made objects into man-made ones). Most
of these seminal works explicitly acknowledged that a major reason
for such a rapid change in the humanenature relationship lies in
the advance of industrial and technological organisations.
Although these organisations of different shapes and sizes are
considered to be a primary instrument by which humans impact
their natural environment(Shrivastava, 1994, p. 705), organisation
studies have paid relatively little attention to the human relation-
ship with the non-human world, and likewise, have largely over-
looked the threats evident in the Anthropocene. A rather small
group of scholars, however, have discussed ecological questions
related to organisations (e.g., Shrivastava, 1994; Jennings and
Zandbergen, 1995; Purser et al., 1995), some with a focus on the
economic organisation (Welford, 1995; Hart, 1995; Clair et al.,
1996), for over two decades (for a summary, see Gladwin et al.,
1995). More recently, continuations to these pioneering studies
have emerged (Valente, 2012; Gosling and Case, 2013; Ezzamel and
Willmott, 2014), but large-scale attention to ecological questions in
organisation theory is yet to come.
3.1. Embeddedness in the ecosystem
In the early 1990s, it became clear that the view offered by
mainstream organisation studies in analysing the surroundings of
organisations was denatured, narrow, and parochial due to its
emphasis on the economic, social, political, and technological as-
pects of organisational environments (Shrivastava, 1994). This
profound critique of the underlying assumptions of the eld led to
an opportunity to reconceptualise the organisational environment
so that the signicance of the non-human world was recognised in
explaining and understanding social activity. The centrality of na-
ture became obvious with the realisation that all individuals and
organisations, as well as sociocultural and political-economic sys-
tems, are embedded in the planetary ecosystem (Starik and Rands,
1995; Ezzamel and Willmott, 2014).
While ecological embeddedness applies to all societies, in-
stitutions and organisations, it also holds true on the individual
level. Whiteman and Cooper (2000, p. 1265) explain this as follows:
To be ecologically embedded as a manager is to personally identify
708
P. Heikkurinen et al. / Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
with the land, to adhere to beliefs of ecological respect, reciprocity,
and caretaking, to actively gather ecological information, and to be
physically located in the ecosystem. The important nding from
the search for ecological organisations is that the degree of
ecological embeddedness is linked to managers' commitment to,
and engagement in an ecological praxis (Whiteman and Cooper,
2000). Thus, instead of making organisational decisions based on
mere technical knowledge, which removes the knower from the
process of knowing(Purser et al., 1995, p. 1060), embeddedness is
related to situational knowledge that comprises rst-hand expe-
rience of local ecosystems (Whiteman and Cooper, 2000). It goes
without saying that the premise of embeddedness radically
changes the manner in which the humanenature relationship is
perceived and organisations are managed (see Tilley, 2000).
3.2. Dependency on the ecosystem
Instead of presupposing nature is something distinct from hu-
manity and an innite pool of resources for economic, or other
human activity, humankind has been forced to admit that ecosys-
tems are nite (Georgescu-Roegen, 1975; Daly, 1979) with material
boundaries (Rockstrom et al., 2009; Steffen et al., 2015), and the
parts are dependent on the whole (Naess, [1974] 1989). As human
organisations receive a number of inputs from various ecosystems,
including air, water, land, minerals, energy, animals, plants, and
microbial life(Starik and Rands, 1995, p. 917) that are critical to
their existence and success (Hart, 1995), the material dependency
of organisations on the planetary ecosystem became obvious. In
other words, the ecosphere provides the conditions essential to the
existence of humans and organisations (Shrivastava, 1995), as well
as those required to conduct economic or any other activity (Starik
and Rands, 1995).
In their study, Starik and Rands (1995, p. 928) demonstrated
how organizations have environmentally oriented interactions
with other levels and systems, and [how] these are integrated in
[] a web of relationships. This insight signies a shift from
atomistic and reductionist ideas to perceiving interconnectedness:
all actors in the ecosystems are connected (Valente, 2012; Newton,
2002). Many ecologically oriented organisation scholars have
employed the notion of interdependency to describe the relation-
ship between human organisations and the natural environment
(Newton, 2002; Valente, 2012; Ezzamel and Willmott, 2014), while
others have refrained from the use of the term (e.g., Starik and
Rands, 1995; Purser et al., 1995). According to Gladwin et al.
(1995), this disparity can be explained by a difference in ontolog-
ical stances. Ecocentric theorists assume that an entity (e.g., an
economic organisation) that is embedded in the ecosystem is
dependent on the ecosystem; however, the whole ecosystem is not
dependent on every single part of it. That is to say, life on the planet
may well continue without any human organisation, but a human
organisation cannot continue without the planet. However,
organised human actions undoubtedly have an effect on local and
global ecosystems as all objects are interconnected, and thus a
degree of interdependency can be argued, but to propose an
equivalent interdependency between objects would be a fallacy.
Hence, it is posited that certain objects (e.g., the Earth) are more
dependent on other objects (e.g., the sun) than others are (e.g., a
business organisation).
3.3. Value of the ecosystem
While anthropocentric organisation studies continue the con-
struction of an ontological hierarchy and a moral order, where
humans are above or apart from the ecosystem (Purser et al., 1995),
ecocentric theorists respectfully consider all human organisations
as subordinate to the planetary ecosystem. In ecocentrism, nature
as a whole is more important than humans, as humans are simply
one animal species in the ecosystem(Ketola, 2008, p. 426). This
reverse in the construction of the ontological and moral hierarchy is
not favoured by most relational theorists (e.g., Newton, 2002), as
for them the world will remain at at all points(Latour, 1996, p.
240). Despite neglecting the difference in the relations between the
whole and its parts, a at ontology is an important step away from
anthropocentrism, but it does not extend to ecocentrism, which
broadens the idea of community to include ecological wholes (such
as forests, wetlands, lakes and deserts) and also extends moral
value to ecological organisms (Purser et al., 1995). This broadened
view is radically different from the prevailing understandings of
value, where any non-instrumental value in the non-human world
is received with anxiety.
While anthropocentrism can also work as a basis for developing
an ecological conscience when motivated by concerns about
intergenerational equity and justice (Johnson, 1988, p. 610), major
problems arise from anthropocentrism for the ecological organi-
sation. The main problem with anthropocentrism is not that it is
human-centred (Purser et al., 1995, p. 1054), or even that its pro-
ponents view nature instrumentally, but with proponentsten-
dency to view human beings as sole locus of value and measure of
all things' (Purser and Montuori, 1996, p. 611). A further problem
with the largely prevalent anthropocentrism in organisational
theory (Ezzamel and Willmott, 2014) and practice (Tilley, 2000) is
that it inuences the code of ethics towards nature by essentially
denying that nature could have any inherent worth (Purser et al.,
1995). This, of course, has severe consequences for how humans
interact with the non-human world.
A few organisation scholars have lately started to raise questions
concerning the reective dismissal of the anthropocentric ethos.
For instance, Wright et al. (2013, p. 647) ask: how can we imagine
alternatives to our current path of ever escalating greenhouse gas
emissions and economic growth?Gosling and Case (2013, p. 716)
suggest that the social dreaming found in many traditional cultures
may offer us a route to discover meanings that are not accessible
within normal conscious rationality, like a non-anthropocentric
moral frame. Similarly, Ezzamel and Willmott (2014, p. 2) suggest
that unclosing the ethical register invites novel thinking about
established forms of knowledge, and thereby opens up new vistas
of theory development and empirical investigations, and impor-
tantly for the present research, attentiveness to the ethical register
is seen to invite radical reection on a dominant, anthropocentric
value-orientation(Ezzamel and Willmott, 2014, p. 1). A desired
outcome of these reections could be an ecocentric ontology and
an ethical frame that encompasses extended and deepened care for
humans as well as non-humans (cf. Naess, 1997).
Table 1 summarises the central premises in the previous eco-
centric organisation literature and the conceptualisation of
humanenature relationships. Next, the paper proposes and dis-
cusses three essential qualities of all objects (mixing humans and
non-humans), derived from object-oriented and ecological phi-
losophies, to complement ecocentric theorising.
4. Essential qualities of objects for ecocentric theorising
As discussed above, previous studies on ecocentrism assume
organisational embeddedness in, and dependency on, the plane-
tary ecosystem (and also regional ecosystems), and enable a de-
parture from anthropocentrism. In terms of the humanenature
relationship, the premise of embeddedness of the ecosystem suggests
that human and man-made objects are embedded in non-human
and non-man-made objects, while the premise of dependency on
the ecosystem denotes that the human and man-made objects are
P. Heikkurinen et al. / Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
709
Table 1
The table illustrates the central premises in the ecocentric organisation literature and the consequent conceptualisations of humanenature relationships.
Central premise
Embeddedness in the ecosystem
Dependency on the ecosystem
Value of the ecosystem
Description of the
premise
Conceptualisation of
humanenature
relationships
Humans and their organisations are
embedded in ecosystems
Human and man-made objects are
embedded in non-human and non-man-
made objects
Humans and their organisations are
dependent on ecosystems
Human and man-made objects are
dependent on non-human and non-man-
made objects
Humans and their organisations are not the only source
of intrinsic value
In addition to human and man-made objects, non-
human and non-man-made objects can also hold
intrinsic value
dependent on non-human and non-man-made objects. Moreover,
with regard to the premise of value of the ecosystem, non-human
and non-man-made objects may also hold intrinsic value (Table 1).
But since ecocentric theory attracts accusations of dualism by
maintaining the analytical separation between humans and non-
humans, normativity through its calls for radical change, and an
unsatisfactory representation of nature (Newton, 2002), reima-
gining the ontological basis on ecocentric theorising is a worth-
while exercise.
4.1. Autonomy of objects
One way to avoid the often-problematized humanenature and
subjecteobject dualism in ecocentric thought (Guattari, 1989;
Newton, 2002) is to consider both human subjects and nature-
objects equally as objects among other objects. This radical idea
of object-oriented philosophy asserts that an enquiry cannot be
merely about the humans in the world, but must encompass other
things and objects (such as crude oil and the oceans), including
their fundamental relations and characteristics (Harman, 2002,
2009). So far many elds of research, including material culture
studies, have ignored factors like the achievements and impacts of
[non-human] living organisms (Ingold, 2012).
The distinction between the notions of things and objects
should be noted. For Ingold (2012), objects are completed forms
that stand over and against the perceiver and block further
movement. He rejects the notion of the object and takes materiality
for what it isemade and nishedeand turns to things to emphasise
the gatherings of materials in movement, as distinct from objects.
In Ingold's (2012) ecology of materials, a focus on the life of ma-
terials prioritises the processes of production over those of con-
sumption. Ingold thus insists on a radical distinction between
object and thing, drawing inspiration primarily from an inuential
essay, entitled The Thing by Heidegger ([1971] 2001, p. 165e182).
For Harman (2009) again, all things are objects. Thus real objects
include those things without matter and relation. And the real
objects [] withdraw from all human view and even from all re-
lations with each other(Harman (2009, p. 195), making the
essential qualities that this paper seeks to outline rather more a
matter of perception than actuality.
Another crucial difference is that while Ingold's (2011) largely
enquires into what things do, Harman (2009) seeks to understand
what objects are. For an ecological organisation, both tasks are
denitely important. In the present enquiry, however, the focus is
on the latter as the study seeks to complement ecocentric thought
with a set of essential qualities common to all objects. These qual-
ities are within the object itself, not to be found in its relation to
other objects (Harman, 2009).
Object-oriented philosophy differs in an important way from
the relational tradition (e.g., actor-network theorising by Latour
(1996, 2005), Johnson (1988)), as it does not consider objects as
fully dened by their relationships with other objects, but views
objects as entities that have a certain autonomy (Harman, 2002,
2009, see also Morin, [1994] 2008). In other words, when
compared to relational ontologies (e.g., Latour, 2005; Johnson,
1988), a distinctive feature of the object orientation is that
objects are not fully dened by their relationships with other ob-
jects, but have a degree of autonomy (Harman, 2002, 2009; Pierides
and Woodman, 2012). Harman (2009, p. 132), one of the key con-
tributors of speculative realism, explains objects and their relations
as follows:
[...] there are countless actors of different sizes and types,
constantly duelling and negotiating with each other. But objects
are not dened by their relations: instead they are what enter
into relations in the rst place, and their allies can never fully
mine their ores. In Heideggerian terms, objects enter relations
but withdraw from them as well; objects are built of compo-
nents, but exceed those components. Things exist not in rela-
tion, but in a strange sort of vacuum from which they only partly
emerge into relation.
However, such autonomy is relative: we will have to conceive
the system in its relation with its environment, in its relation with
time, in its relation nally with the observer/conceiver(Morin
[1977] 1992, p. 123). Human and man-made objects are
embedded in non-human and non-man-made objects. While the
existential phenomenological tradition of Heidegger ([1927] 1962)
is also inclined to consider objects as subordinate to human access
to them, the present study draws a non-anthropocentric ontolog-
ical line, where objects may not only exist but also thrive inde-
pendently of human perception and presence. This means that not
all objects depend on the subject (cf. Morin, [1994] 2008, p. 108),
and it is exactly because of this that the autonomy of objects is
highly relevant to the task of developing ecocentric theorising, as it
offers an exit from the anthropocentric and dualistic conceptual
frames of thought.
Humans should no longer speak of relations between people
and things, because people are things too (Ingold, 2012) but should
instead address everything as an object (Harman, 2009). The
importance of this post-human ontological turn is that when each
thing becomes an object, the material and non-human worlds, and
their relations with other objects, are also included in the analysis
(Pierides and Woodman, 2012). For an organisational analysis, this
signies that all objects and their relations matter(Pierides and
Woodman, 2012, p. 663), as they become full members of the
world community (Purser et al., 1995). This helps not only to ac-
count for the missing living (and non-living) organisms in the
scholarly analysis, but it also helps to erase the division between
ecological and social, and encourages people to view organisms as
parts of an intertwined process of becoming (Ingold and Palsson,
2013). Things are not mere objects of perception, but part of the
world-in-formation. In other words, rather than considering
humans as subjects and observers, becoming prompts us to view
humans as objects and participants (Ingold, 2011), as well as beings
with the capability to act as the observers of the observer (Morin,
[1994] 2008).
4.2. Intrinsicality of objects
The ethical register of theory building often tends to be over-
looked (Ezzamel and Willmott, 2014), but in this paper axiological
710
P. Heikkurinen et al. / Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
questions are considered an integral part of the ontological outline.
When independent non-human entities enter the equation, the
traditional anthropocentric assumptions are likely to be challenged
(Pierides and Woodman, 2012). However, the inclusion of non-
human objects in the analysis, although signalling that analysis is
taking the materiality of organisations seriously, does not mean
that an ecocentric ethos would automatically emerge. In fact, there
is a danger the post-human approaches develop into post-humane,
and perhaps violent, forms of actions unless the question of value is
explicitly addressed.
The second quality of objects adds depth to the ecocentric
organisation theory by suggesting that every object (including
agents such as ants or humans, structures such as buildings or re-
ligions, and processes such as thinking or life) has intrinsic value.
Following intrinsicalism (Gladwin et al., 1995), this quality of ob-
jects can be called intrinsicality. It is important to note here that the
intrinsicality of objects does not denote that all objects are proper,
good or right in the ethical sense. Nevertheless, by assuming this
quality is present, no object is considered merely an instrument for,
or means to, another object: instead objects become valued in
themselves. This signies that non-human objects are valuable
independently of human objects (Naess, 1973, [1974] 1989) and
fosters the view of a human object as an object among others. In
contrast to the anthropocentric form of thought, ecocentric
scholars are able to escape the humanenature value dichotomy
through a premise of inherent equality and justice between all
objects.
According to Naess (1973), such broadened egalitarianism,
however, only works in principle. This is because any realistic
praxis necessitates some killing, exploitation, and suppression
(Naess, 1973, p. 95). Moreover, Naess ([1974] 1989, p. 95e96) ex-
plains the inclusive form of egalitarianism as follows:
The ecological eld worker acquires a deep-seated respect, even
veneration, for ways and forms of life. He reaches an under-
standing from within, a kind of understanding that others
reserve for fellow men and for a narrow selection of ways and
forms of life. To the ecological eld worker, the equal right to live
and blossom is an intuitively clear and obvious value axiom. Its
restriction to humans is an anthropocentrism with detrimental
effects upon the life quality of humans themselves. This quality
depends in part upon the deep pleasure and satisfaction we
receive from close partnership with other forms of life. The
attempt to ignore our dependence and to establish a master-
slave role has contributed to the alienation of man from himself.
In the above excerpt, Naess illustrates how the understanding of
the intrinsicality of objects relates to both human ethics and aes-
thetics, and how humans have a natural attraction to life. Ingold
(2011, p. 39), somewhat similarly, connects value and senses as
he states that nothing, however, better illustrates the value placed
upon a sedentary perception of the world, mediated by the alleg-
edly superior senses of vision and hearing, and unimpeded by any
haptic or kinaesthetic sensation through the fee(Ingold, 2011, p.
39). That is, ethics and aesthetics are to a great extent intertwined
(Bateson, [1972] 2000; Kagan, 2010). While human objects have the
skill of aesthetic evaluation, which surely helps people to perceive
value in the non-human world, it does not denote that the value of
objects is dependent on humans assigning such value to objects. In
Naess' ([1974] 1989) terms, it instead refers to the human realisa-
tion of the inherent value in objects, and its consequences for
humans (e.g., in terms of aesthetic experiences). The quality of
intrinsicality hence contrasts with instrumentalism, which
views the value of objects only in relation to other objects.
While the value of objects largely unfolds in relation to others
(Bateson, [1972] 2000; Latour, 2005), intrinsicality posits that value
is a quality rather than a relation.
Perhaps somewhat paradoxically, humans might nd them-
selves forced to leave the still largely prevalent anthropocentric
premises behind in order to save the human species while not
destroying others. In practice, this would rst mean recognising the
human place within the complex ecosphere, then admitting
the limitations of human intellectual mechanisms in understanding
the complexity, and third, proceeding with precaution and respect
for all objects. But leaving anthropocentrism behind also necessi-
tates and implies an ecosophical language that turns the enquiry
away from human-centred discourse and practices based on the
instrumentalisation of objects. Fortunately, there is an increased
awareness of the connection between scientic truth, on the one
hand, and beauty and morality, on the other: that if a man entertain
false opinions regarding his own nature [or arguably regarding any
nature], he will be led thereby to courses of action which will be in
some profound sense immoral and ugly(Bateson, [1972] 2000,
p. 265).
4.3. Uniqueness of objects
The rationale for considering everything as an object and
assuming all objects come with intrinsic value comes from the
realisation that an object's existence (and becoming) is always
exceptional. Objects, be they persons, owers, events, sounds, or
other phenomena, disclose in a specic time and place a horizon
that is always unique. To ontologically arrive at this idea of
uniqueness, objects are considered to be irreducible to their con-
stituent parts (Naess, [1974] 1989; Harman, 2009). For example,
any attempt to undermine an object e in thought, or with a gun, or
with heat, or with the ravages of time or global warming e will not
get at the withdrawn essence of the object(Morton, 2011, p. 150). It
is crucial to note that objects cannot be rejected and reduced to
anything: objects are what objects are. This signies that objects
are irreplaceable (Naess, [1974] 1989) and non-substitutable (Daly,
1979).
The substitutability of objects is often assumed in economics
and reductionist ecological studies (Heikkurinen and Bonnedahl,
2013). However, objects such as natural and human capital are
not substitutable but only complementary (Daly, 1979), if even that.
For an ecological enquiry, the non-substitutability factor is of vital
importance, as man-made objects such as thoughts, machines and
economic processes cannot substitute for non-man-made objects
(such as stars, forests and species), and vice versa. Daly (1996, p. 76)
explains this non-substitutability vividly:
One way to make an argument is to assume the opposite and
show that it is absurd. If man-made capital were a near perfect
substitute for natural capital, then natural capital would be a
near perfect substitute for man-made capital. But if so, there
would have been no reason to accumulate man-made capital in
the rst place, since we were endowed by nature with a near
perfect substitute. But historically we did accumulate
man-made capital e precisely because it is complementary to
natural capital. [...] Man-made capital is itself a physical trans-
formation of natural resources which come from natural capital.
Therefore, producing more of the alleged substitute (man-made
capital), physically requires more of the very thing being
substituted for (natural capital) e the dening condition of
complementarity!
This paper thus assumes that the essence and relations of all
objects are at best complementary rather than substitutable. For
instance, it is common sense that objects such as sawmills cannot
P. Heikkurinen et al. / Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
711
substitute for stocks of wood (Daly, 1979, 1992), and the other way
around, which necessitates rethinking the role of objects and the
current industrial practices that transform objects at an increasing
pace. And what follows the irreducibility and non-substitutability
of objects is the quality of uniqueness. The uniqueness of objects
directs scholars away from any reductionist mode of organisation
studies towards more inclusive frameworks (see e.g., Purser et al.,
1995; Reed, 2005; Lozano, 2008), and guides them to proceed
with caution when organising and managing objects, as well as
encouraging respect for the exceptionality of all objects.
5. Discussion on object-oriented ecosophy
As the essential qualities of objects in this study are derived
from object-oriented philosophy (Harman, 2002, 2009) and
ecological philosophy (Naess, 1973, [1974] 1989). The three-point
outline could be labelled object-oriented ecosophy. In the
following, the reasons why the emergence of ontological discussion
in ecological studies could be valuable, and the implications of the
outline for ecological theory and practice are discussed.
Autonomy is very relevant to ecocentric theory, as the notion of
autonomy does not correspond to the old notion of freedom, which
was to a certain extent immaterial and detached from constraints
and physical contingencies(Morin, [1994] 2008, p. 69). According
to Morin ([1994] 2008, p. 69), it is, on the contrary, a notion closely
linked to that of dependency, and the latter is inseparable from the
notion of self-organization. That is, objects are emergent, a quality
that might be measured or registered by their relationships, but
can never be fully dened by them(Harman, 2009, p. 143). This
quality enables scholars to describe and prescribe different
agencies for objects, yet keep them embedded in the ecosystem. For
example, it is commonly accepted that without a degree of au-
tonomy, no moral responsibility for sustainability (or any other
end) can be assigned or assumed. Further, when ethics is consid-
ered an essential element in achieving sustainability (de Paula and
Calavanti, 2000), then moral agency is needed to enable, or at least
support, the change. Thus, it is vital that the degree of autonomy
can be used to explain different agencies in scientic enquiry
instead of claiming full interdependency between objects, which
leaves little or no room for moral agency (or quality) in objects (see
e.g., Latour, 2002).
However, without a degree of autonomy, objects lack the ability
to act and to explore their full potential. The idea of the degree of
autonomy urges researchers and practitioners of ecological
organising to gradually move from questions such as how are ob-
jects related to each other?to more practically relevant questions
such as what are the implications if all objects are assumed to have
agency beyond their relations to other objects, and thus also
beyond human comprehension?Consequently, humans respon-
sible for organisations become better equipped to appreciate the
idea that they need not only to understand how objects are related
to each other in the production system, but also to understand the
capability of all objects to surprise the production system with their
inherent agency.
While a degree of autonomy is an essential part of object-
oriented ecosophy, it becomes ecologically strong only when
complemented with the other two qualities. By realising that ob-
jects are not substitutes for other objects and cannot be reduced to
any other object, the quality of uniqueness becomes accessible, and
when objects disclose uniquely in a specic time and place horizon,
it calls for the theory and practice to respect and embrace their
exceptionality, including transformation, change, decomposition
and death, that is, also the vulnerability and fatality of objects.
This quality should prompt both researchers and managers to
scrutinise the ethics of depriving any object of its agency or
existence. The focal implication for organisational practices would
thus be to proceed with caution when organising and managing
objects. Assuming objects, such as people, animals, forests, chairs,
activities, ideas and sounds, are entities that are irreducible and
non-substitutable invites us to consider that objects possess not
only instrumental value dependent on other objects but, most
importantly, value in themselves. This kind of inherent value
translates to the quality of intrinsicality. The main implication of
intrinsicality for organisational enquiry is that it releases objects
from the instrumental rationale, and signies the right of objects to
disclose on their own, that is, to live and ourish.
Moreover, object-oriented ecosophy and the quality of intrinsi-
cality hold crucial instrumental value for an enquiry into ecological
organisation. In other words, if it is to imagine, practice, and
manage those organisational orderings that are to stay within
material boundaries, humankind has to embrace the existence of all
objects for their own sake and therefore to admit their intrinsic
value. In the light of anthropocentric thought, this rationale might
seem paradoxical for two reasons. First, although instrumentality
and intrinsicality usually (if not always) coexist in an object, they
are often thought of in dualistic terms, as opposites. Nevertheless,
there is no reason to think that they could not coexist in an object.
Second, the rationale behind intrinsicality is supported with an
instrumental logic dictating that if people are to imagine and
practice those ecological orderings, they need to embrace the ex-
istence of all objects for their own sake. Again, teleological argu-
mentation (which claims something for the sake of an end) can be
considered to conict with the idea of intrinsicality only if intrin-
sicality is presumed to be something that is antithetical to
instrumentality.
An ecological turn based on these ecocentric premises repre-
sents a radical departure from mainstream organisation theory and
shallow environmental turns within and around it. There is little
doubt that importing ecological concepts into organisation theory
will involve a major reorientation (Purser et al., 1995), which will
take time. It is, however, rather encouraging to note that ecologi-
cally advanced ontological turns are occurring in sociology (Urry,
2011) and economics (Spash, 2012). However, the question re-
mains whether ecocentric theory must still be developed on the
outskirts of contemporary organisation theory, or whether society
will open up and begin taking the threats of the Anthropocene
seriously.
Be that as it may, the paper considers that given the proposed
set of essential qualities of objects (see Table 2 for a summary),
organisational scholars would be willing and able to build practi-
cally relevant and ecologically advanced theories that consider the
non-human and material realms as integral parts of the analysis
without falling into the trap of dualism or unsatisfactory repre-
sentations of nature (see Newton, 2002; Hanna, 1996). Further-
more, such a descriptive outline could offer a response to the
critique of ecocentric theorising being just normative ecological
ordering that is doomed to fail, since it is merely an ontology that is
not considered to be over-encompassing or forced on anyone. It
may or may not be realised.
The ontological outline suggested in this paper escapes the
kind of realism where reality is objective and accessible to
humans objectively, as well as the kind of antirealism where
realities are socially constructed and always relative to subjective
human interpretation. The philosophical position of the present
study decentralises the human subject by assuming that reality
may be objective but knowledge about it only subjective. A sig-
nicant motivation for leaving the antirealism behind comes from
noting that these positions are not equipped to face the ongoing
ecological catastrophe (Bryant et al., 2011) that is the
Anthropocene.
712
P. Heikkurinen et al. / Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
Table 2
The table illustrates the essential qualities of objects and the implications to ecocentric theory and practice.
Quality of
objects
Autonomy
Intrinsicality
Uniqueness
Underlying
assumption
and key
literature
Description of
the quality
Theoretical
implication
Practical
implication
Objects are not fully dened by their relationships Objects are not considered to be merely instruments Objects are irreducible (Harman, 2002; Naess,
with other objects but have a degree of autonomy for, or means to, other objects but have value in [1974] 1989) and non-substitutable (Daly,
(Harman, 2002, 2009)
themselves (Naess, [1974] 1989)
1979)
All objects have a degree of autonomy
All objects are ends in themselves
All objects are
unique
Some objects are more autonomous than others No object should be treated merely as a means
Objects disclose in a specic time and place
horizon
Autonomy can be used to explain and assign
Intrinsicality releases objects from instrumental Uniqueness suggests precaution in organising
different (moral) agencies, i.e. objects' ability to act rationale, and signies the right of objects to disclose activities and the conservation of ecosystems,
and explore their fullest potential
on their own; to live and blossom
as well as embracing the diversity of objects
It has been argued that if humans are to move to ecocentric
ontologies, they need more than a popular, observer-style under-
standing of ecology (Purser et al., 1995, also Morin, [1994] 2008).
Thus, in addition to embedding social actors in the ecosystem
(Whiteman and Cooper, 2000), recognising the interconnectedness
of all actors in that ecosystem, (Valente, 2012; Newton, 2002), and
advancing ethical considerations to encompass the non-human
world (Gosling and Case, 2013; Ezzamel and Willmott, 2014), ob-
jects would have a metaphysical footing of their own. Objects exist
as autonomous units, but they also exist in conjunction with their
qualities, accidents, relations, and movements without being
reducible to these(Harman, 2009, p. 156). Becoming aware of the
qualities of objects necessitates engaging with the objects in a
direct and open manner, that is, encountering them without
instrumentalisation.
While the popular knowledge of objects is a sort of spectator
epistemology that assumes that by withdrawing from participation
in the world, objects can be described and represented as if there
were no subjective observer (with values, feelings, etc.)(Purser
et al., 1995, p. 1059), the situational knowing that object-oriented
ecosophy hints at does not exclude subjectivity from objects or
values from ontology. Subjective sentiments such as values in fact
play a central role in the ecocentric ontology that is not dominated
by, or limited to, instrumental rationality (Purser et al., 1995).
Furthermore, several scholars have pondered whether the
groundlessness that characterises modern living is preventing
humans from developing deeper understandings of, and relations
to, objects (Heidegger, [1945] 2010; von Wright, 1978; Ingold,
2011). If so, then re-establishing grounds for time- and space-
sensitive knowing by anchoring practices in closer proximity
would be warranted.
6. Conclusions
The current research indicates that the new geological era of the
Anthropocene calls for a new ontology to guide the organisation of
human activities. The ontology proposed here takes a realist and
ecocentric turn to avoid the pitfalls of the antirealist and anthro-
pocentric approaches. Drawing from object-oriented (Harman,
2002, 2009) and ecological philosophies (Naess, 1973, [1974]
1989), the study proposes three essential qualities common to all
objects, namely autonomy, intrinsicality, and uniqueness. The onto-
logical outline formed by these three points responds to the
critique of ecocentric organisation studies. It demonstrates how to
avoid the humanenature dualism by considering each thing an
object while still arriving at an ecologically relevant view of reality.
The outline labelled object-oriented ecosophy facilitates
explaining and assigning different agencies depending on the de-
gree of autonomy, the release of objects from an instrumental
ethical rationale, and the reasoning behind exercising caution
around objects and encouraging their conservation. When the
suggested qualities are assumed in organising activities, objects
become capable of unfolding in their own ways (autonomy), acquire
rights to exist on their own (intrinsicality), and are respected for
what they are (uniqueness).
The current study's main contribution to ecological organisation
theory and practice is to provide a framework for reimagining the
objecteobject relations central to the peaceful coexistence of objects.
This includes the reconsideration of the relationship between
humans and the natural environment, and the consequent need to
reorganise production activity in a manner that embraces the di-
versity of objects. The ongoing growth of human economic activity
has had a severe impact in terms of reducing the diversity of life,
leading to a call for a degrowth society(Daly, 1996; Latouche, 2009;
Jackson, 2011). Object-oriented ecosophy offers an ontological outline
for this transition. If the suggested qualities of objects are perceived
in organisations, then organisations are likely to radically reduce the
instrumentalisation of objects, including the use of so-called natural
resources or capital. In practice, the outline is to signify a decrease in
the rate of material throughput needed to reach sustainability
(Georgescu-Roegen,1975; Daly,1996) and an ecological organisation.
The limitations of this paper relate to the conceptual nature of
the study. Whether the proposed ontological outline is actually
suited to promote sustainability and would lead to desirable
changes in organisational practice is a question that must be
explored empirically. Future studies might therefore test the model
in organisations, and encompass further theoretical work on the
qualities and activities of objects.
Funding
The research undertaken by Pasi Heikkurinen, Jenny Rinkinen,
Kristoffer Wilen, and Toni Ruuska received no specic grant from
any funding agency in the public, commercial, or not-for-prot
sectors. The work of Timo Jarvensivu was funded by a Tekes (the
Finnish Funding Agency for Innovation) research project Ener-
gizing Urban Ecosystems.
Acknowledgements
Previous versions of this paper were presented at two interna-
tional colloquia: (1) the Finnish Society for Environmental Social
Science (YHYS), sub-theme Methods of Framing in Environmental
Policy and Sustainable Consumption Researchin November 2013,
and (2) the European Group for Organizational Studies (EGOS), sub-
theme Things Ain't What They Used to Be: Objects, Relations,
Materialityin June 2014. We wish to thank the organisers and
participants of these events for their valuable comments. We also
P. Heikkurinen et al. / Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
713
want to express our deepest gratitude to the editorial team and the
four anonymous reviewers of this journal for their encouragement
and critical remarks.
References
Ayres, R., van den Berrgh, J., Gowdy, J., 2001. Strong versus weak sustainability.
Environ. Ethics 23, 155e168.
Barnosky, A.D., Matzke, N., Tomiya, S., Wogan, G.O.U., Swartz, B., Quental, T.B.,
Marshall, C., McGuire, J.L., Lindsey, E.L., Maguire, K.C., Mersey, B., Ferrer, E.A.,
2011. Has the Earth's sixth mass extinction already arrived? Nature 471, 51e57.
Barnosky, A.D., Hadly, E.A., Bascompte, J., Berlow, E.L., Brown, J.H., Fortelius, M.,
Getz, W.M., Harte, J., Hastings, A., Marquet, P.A., Martinez, N.D., Mooers, A.,
Roopnarine, P., Vermeij, G., Williams, G.W., Gillespie, R., Kitzes, J., Marshall, C.,
Matzke, N., Mindell, D.P., Revilla, E., Smith, A.B., 2012. Approaching a state shift
in Earth's biosphere. Nature 486, 52e58.
Bateson, G., 2000 [1972]. Steps to an Ecology of Mind. University of Chicago Press,
New York.
Beckerman, W., 1995. How would you like your sustainability, sir? Weak or strong?
A reply to my critics. Environ. Values 4, 167e179.
Bryant, L., Srnicek, N., Harman, G., 2011. The speculative turn: continental materi-
alism and realism. re.press, Melbourne.
Carson, R., 1962. Silent Spring. Houghton Mifin, Boston.
Ceballos, G., Ehrlich, P.R., Barnosky, A.D., García, A., Pringle, R.M., Palmer, T.M., 2015.
Accelerated modern humaneinduced species losses: entering the sixth mass
extinction. Sci. Adv. 1, e1400253.
Clair, J.A., Milliman, J., Whelan, K.S., 1996. Toward an environmentally sensitive
ecophilosophy for business management. Organ. Environ. 9, 289e326.
Crutzen, P.J., 2002. Geology of mankind. Nature 415, 2323.
Crutzen, P.J., Steffen, W., 2003. How long have we been in the Anthropocene era?
Clim. Change 61, 251e257.
Crutzen, P.J., Stoermer, E.F., 2000. The Anthropocene. Glob. Change Newsl. 41, 17e18.
Cunha, M.P.e., Rego, A., Vieira da Cunha, J., 2008. Ecocentric management: an up-
date. Corp. Soc. Responsib. Environ. Manag. 15, 311e321.
Daly, H.E., 1979. Entropy, growth and the political economy of scarcity. In:
Smith, V.K. (Ed.), Scarcity and Growth Reconsidered. John Hopkins U. Press,
Baltimore, pp. 67e94.
Daly, H.E., 1992. Steady-state Economics. Earthscan, London.
Daly, H.E., 1996. Beyond Growth. Beacon Press, Boston.
de Paula, G.O., Cavalcanti, R.N., 2000. Ethics: essence for sustainability. J. Clean.
Product. 8, 109e117.
Ellul, J., 1964 [1954]. The Technological Society (La technique ou l'enjeu du siecle)
(translated by Merton, R.K.). Vintage Books, New York.
Emerson, R., 1836. Nature. James Munroe and Company, Boston.
Ezzamel, M., Willmott, H., 2014. Registering the ethicalin organization theory
formation: towards the disclosure of an invisible force. Organ. Stud. 35,
1013e1039.
Fleetwood, S., 2005. Ontology in organization and management studies: a critical
realist perspective. Organization 12, 197e222.
Georgescu-Roegen, N., 1975. Energy and economic myths. South. Econ. J. 41,
347e381.
Gladwin, T.N., Kennelly, J.J., Krause, T.S., 1995. Shifting paradigms for sustainable
development: implications for management theory and research. Acad. Manag.
Rev. 20, 874e907.
Goodland, R., Daly, H., 1996. Environmental sustainability: universal and non-
negotiable. Ecol. Appl. 6, 1002e1017.
Gosling, J., Case, P., 2013. Social dreaming and ecocentric ethics: sources of non-
rational insight in the face of climate change catastrophe. Organization 20,
705e721.
Guattari, F., 1989. The three ecologies. New Form. 8, 131e147.
Hanna, M.D., 1996. Environmentally responsible managerial behavior: is ecocen-
trism a prerequisite. Acad. Manag. Rev. 21, 796e799.
Harman, G., 2002. Tool-being: Heidegger and the metaphysics of objects. Open
Court Publishing, Chicago.
Harman, G., 2009. Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics. re.press,
Prahran.
Hart, S.L., 1995. A natural-resource-based view of the rm. Acad. Manag. Rev. 20,
986e1014.
Heidegger, M., 1962 [1927]. Being and Time (Sein und Zeit) (translated by Mac-
qarrie, J., Robinson, E.). Blackwell Publishing, Malden.
Heidegger, M., 2001 [1971]. Poetry, Language, Thought (Das Gegeneinander von
Welt und Erde ist ein Streit) (translated by Hofstadter, A.). Harper & Row, New
York.
Heidegger, M., 2010 [1945] (Translated by Davis, B.W.). Country Path Conversations
[Gesamtausgabe, vol. 77]. Indiana University Press, Bloomington.
Heikkurinen, P., Bonnedahl, K.J., 2013. Corporate responsibility for sustainable
development: a review and conceptual comparison of market- and stakeholder-
oriented strategies. J. Clean. Prod. 43, 191e198.
Holt, R., Mueller, F., 2011. Wittgenstein, Heidegger and drawing lines in organization
studies. Organ. Stud. 32, 67e84.
Hornborg, A., 2014. Ecological economics, marxism, and technological progress:
some explorations of the conceptual foundations of theories of ecologically
unequal exchange. Ecol. Econ. 105, 11e18.
Ingold, T., 2011. Being Alive: Essays on Movement, Knowledge and Description.
Taylor & Francis, New York.
Ingold, T., 2012. Toward an ecology of materials. Annu. Rev. Anthropol. 41, 427e442.
Ingold, T., Palsson, G., 2013. Biosocial Becomings: Integrating Social and Biological
Anthropology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
IPCC (Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change), 2014. 5th Assessment Report.
Climate Change 2014: Impacts, Adaption, and Vulnerability.
Jackson, T., 2011. Prosperity without Growth: Economics for a Finite Planet.
Earthscan, New York.
Jennings, P.D., Zandbergen, P.A., 1995. Ecologically sustainable organizations: an
institutional approach. Acad. Manag. Rev. 20, 1015e1052.
Johnson, J., 1988. Mixing humans and nonhumans together: the sociology of a door-
closer. Soc. Probl. 35, 298e310.
Kagan, S., 2010. Cultures of sustainability and the aesthetics of the pattern that
connects. Futures 42, 1094e1101.
Ketola, T., 2008. A holistic corporate responsibility model: integrating values, dis-
courses and actions. J. Bus. Ethics 80, 419e435.
Koot, L., Grootveld, M., 2015. Interview with Graham Harman on the Anthropocene.
In: Sonic Acts Research Series #10, Anthropocene Objects, Art and Politics.
Available at: http://www.sonicacts.com/portal/anthropocene-objects-art-and-
politics-1.
Latouche, S., 2009. Farewell to Growth. Polity Press, Cambridge.
Latour, B., 1996. On interobjectivity. Mind Cult. Act. 3, 228e245.
Latour, B., 2002. Morality and technology: the end of the means (translated by
Venn, C.). Theory Cult. Soc. 19, 247e260.
Latour, B., 2005. Reassembling the Social-an Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory.
Reassembling the Social-an Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Lorek, S., Spangenberg, J.H., 2014. Sustainable consumption within a sustainable
economyebeyond green growth and green economies. J. Clean. Prod. 63,
33e44.
Lozano, R., 2008. Envisioning sustainability three-dimensionally. J. Clean. Prod. 16,
1838e1846.
MA (Millennium Ecosystem Assessment), 2005. Ecosystems and Human Well-
being: Synthesis. Island Press, Washington.
Maki, U., 2008. Scientic realism and ontology. New Palgrave Dict. Econ. 7, 334e341.
Martinez-Alier, J., 2014. Environmentalism, currents of. In: D'Alisa, G., Demaria, F.,
Kallis, G. (Eds.), Degrowth: a Vocabulary for a New Era. Routledge, London,
pp. 37e40.
Marx, K., 1992 [1867]. Capital Volume 1: A Critique of Political Economy (Das
Kapital: Kritik der politischen Okonomie) (translated by Fowkes, B.). Penguin
Classics, New York.
Morin, E., 1992 [1977]. Method: towards a Study of Humankind: La nature de la
nature (translated by Belanger, J.L.R.). In: The Nature of Nature: La nature de la
nature, vol. 1. Peter Lang, New York.
Morin, E., 2008 [1994]. On Complexity (La complexite humaine) (translated by
Postel, R., Kelly, S.M.). Hampton Press, Cresskill.
Morton, T., 2011. Objects as temporary autonomous zones. Continent 1, 149e155.
Naess, A., 1973. The shallow and the deep, long-range ecology movement. A sum-
mary. Inq. Interdiscip. J. Philos. 16, 95e100.
Naess, A., 1989 [1974]. Ecology, Community and Lifestyle (Økologi, samfunn og
livsstil: utkast til en økoso) (translated by Rothenberg, D.). Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, Camridge.
Naess, A., 1997. Sustainable development and the deep ecology movement. In:
Baker, S., Kousis, M., Richardson, D., Young, S. (Eds.), The Politics of Sustainable
Development: Theory, Policy and Practice within the European Union. Rout-
ledge, London, pp. 61e71.
NASA/GISS (National Aeronautics and Space Administration/Goddard Institute for
Space Studies), 2014. Climate Data. Available at: data.giss.nasa.gov.
Newton, T.J., 2002. Creating the new ecological order? Elias and actor-network
theory. Acad. Manag. Rev. 27, 523e540.
Orlikowski, W.J., 2010. The sociomateriality of organisational life: considering
technology in management research. Camb. J. Econ. 34, 125e141.
Pearce, D.W., Atkinson, G.D., 1993. Capital theory and the measurement of sus-
tainable development: an indicator of weaksustainability. Ecol. Econ. 8,
103e108.
Pierides, D., Woodman, D., 2012. Object-oriented sociology and organizing in the
face of emergency: Bruno Latour, Graham Harman and the material turn. Br. J.
Sociol. 63, 662e679.
Purser, R.E., Montuori, A., 1996. Ecocentrism is in the eye of the beholder. Acad.
Manag. Rev. 21, 611e613.
Purser, R.E., Park, C., Montuori, A., 1995. Limits to anthropocentrism: toward an
ecocentric organization paradigm? Acad. Manag. Rev. 20, 1053e1089.
Reed, M., 2005. Reections on the realist turnin organization and management
studies. J. Manag. Stud. 42, 1621e1644.
Rockstrom, J., Steffen, W., Noone, K., Persson, Å, Chapin III, F.S., Lambin, E.F.,
Lenton, T.M., Scheffer, M., Folke, C., Schellnhuber, H.J., Nykvist, B., de Wit, C.A.,
Hughes, T., van der Leeuw, S., Rodhe, H., Sorlin, S., Snyder, P.K., Costanza, R.,
Svedin, U., Falkenmark, M., Karlberg, L., Corell, R.W., Fabry, V.J., Hansen, J.,
Walker, B., Liverman, D., Richardson, K., Crutzen, P., Foley, J.A., 2009. A safe
operating space for humanity. Nature 461, 472e475.
Schwagerl, C., 2013. Anthropo-scene #1: from Rocks to Thoughts. Next Nature, April
29, 2013. Available at: https://www.nextnature.net/2013/04/anthropo-scene-1-
from-rocks-to-thoughts/.
714
P. Heikkurinen et al. / Journal of Cleaner Production 113 (2016) 705e714
Shrivastava, P., 1994. Castrated environment: greening organizational studies. Or-
gan. Stud. 15, 705e726.
Shrivastava, P., 1995. The role of corporations in achieving ecological sustainability.
Acad. Manag. Rev. 20, 936e960.
Spash, C.L., 2012. New foundations for ecological economics. Ecol. Econ. 77, 36e47.
Starik, M., 1995. Should trees have managerial standing? Toward stakeholder status
for non-human nature. J. Bus. Ethics 14, 207e217.
Starik, M., Rands, G.P., 1995. Weaving an integrated web: multilevel and multi-
system perspectives of ecologically sustainable organizations. Acad. Manag.
Rev. 20, 908e935.
Steffen, W., Crutzen, P.J., McNeill, J.R., 2007. The Anthropocene: are humans now
overwhelming the great forces of nature. Ambio J. Hum. Environ. 36, 614e621.
Steffen, W., Richardson, K., Rockstrom, J., Cornell, S.E., Fetzer, I., Bennett, E.M.,
Biggs, R., Carpenter, S.R., de Vries, W., de Wit, C.A., Folke, C., Gerten, D.,
Heinke, J., Mace, G.M., Persson, L.M., Ramanathan, V., Reyers, B., Sorlin, S., 2015.
Planetary boundaries: guiding human development on a changing planet.
Science 347, 1259855.
Thoreau, H.D., 1854. Walden. Ticknor and Fields, Boston.
Tilley, F., 2000. Small rm environmental ethics: how deep do they go? Bus. Ethics
Eur. Rev. 9, 31e41.
UNEP (United Nations Environment Programme), 2011. Decoupling Natural
Resource Use and Environmental Impacts from Economic Growth. A report of
the working group on decoupling to the International Resource Panel. English
summary. Retrieved from. http://www.unep.org/resourcepanel/Portals/24102/
PDFs/DecouplingENGSummary.pdf.
Urry, J., 2011. Climate Change and Society. Polity Press, Cambridge.
Valente, M., 2012. Theorizing rm adoption of sustaincentrism. Organ. Stud. 33,
563e591.
von Wright, G.H., 1978. Humanismen Som Livshållning (Humanism as an Approach
to Life). Månpocket, Stockholm.
Welford, R., 1995. Environmental Strategy and Sustainable Development: the
Corporate Challenge for the Twenty-rst Century. Routledge, London.
Whiteman, G., Cooper, W.H., 2000. Ecological embeddedness. Acad. Manag. J. 43,
1265e1282.
Wright, C., Nyberg, D., De Cock, C., Whiteman, G., 2013. Future imaginings: orga-
nizing in response to climate change. Organization 20, 647e658.
Wrigley, E.A., 2010. Energy and the English Industrial Revolution. Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, Cambridge.
Zalasiewicza, J., Williams, M., Smith, A., Barry, T.L., Coe, A.L., Bown, P.R., Brenchley, P.,
Cantrill, D., Gale, A., Gibbard, P., Gregory, F.J., Hounslow, M.W., Kerr, A.C.,
Pearson, P., Knox, R., Powell, J., Waters, C., Marshall, J., Oates, M., Rawson, P.,
Stone, P., 2008. Are we now living in the Anthropocene? GSA Today 18, 4e8.